1 Ararr

Ethical Democracy Essays In Social Dynamics Of Trauma

Democracy, ethics and social justice: Implications for secondary school leadership in Kenya

 

 

Julius O. JwanI; Sella T. KisakaII

IKenya Institute of Curriculum Development, Nairobi, Kenya
IIDiscipline of Curriculum Studies, School of Education, University of KwaZulu-Natal, Ashwood, South Africa. sellaterrie01@gmail.com

 

 


ABSTRACT

Principals in Kenyan schools are required to adopt democratic school leadership practises as part of the government policy. Adopting an interpretive case study, this paper set out to explore the application of democracy, ethics and social justice in secondary schools in Kenya. The study was in two phases. Phase one: twelve school principals were interviewed to explore their perspectives on democratic school leadership and establish the rationale for selecting two case schools. PHASE TWO: an in-depth case study was conducted in the two schools. Interviews, focus group discussions, observation and informal conversations were used to generate data. The findings suggest that the principals, teachers and students each perceive and apply democratic school leadership differently based on individual as well as the school socio-cultural context. These contrasting views provide grounds for further discourse on the phenomenon. The paper recommends formal training for principals through in-service courses. Inclusion of democratic school leadership principles in teacher training programmes and an inculcation of democratic school leadership practices/values in the school curriculum for students to create a shared vision and understanding of these concepts for the success of the school

Keywords: democracy; ethics; leadership practices; social justice


 

 

Introduction

The Kenyan Government in adhering to the enactment of the UN charter on the rights of the child, requires school principals to adopt democratic school leadership practices. Similarly, the national goals of education (Republic of Kenya, 1964:21-25) emphasises education that gives opportunities to "every child", "promotes social justice, equality and foster a sense of social responsibility and nationalism." However, despite this policy directive, very little attention has been paid to the practice in schools, coupled with a paucity of research in Kenya and Sub-Saharan Africa on democratic school leadership. The purpose of this paper is to explore the application of democracy, ethics and social justice in secondary schools in Kenya and emanates from a study conducted to establish the students', teachers' and principals' perceptions of democratic school leadership. The literature unpacks the concept democracy, democratic school leadership, ethical rationality and social justice in relation to democratic school leadership.

This study, though conducted in Kenya, appeals to an international readership, and is applicable globally as the key tenets of democracy, ethics and social justice are core values to education practitioners worldwide. Furthermore, democratic school leadership like caring leadership is pegged on valuing people within organisations and could apply to other sectors.

Literature Review

Democracy is an avidly contested concept, thus fruitful discussion about its nature and connection to education practices should acknowledge a diverse range of discursive traditions and allegiances pertaining to it (Fielding, 2007). Studies that explore these and how they are practised in different contexts are essential, and as PA Woods and Gronn (2009) point out, there have always been different ways and means of expressing democratic principles. Nevertheless, democracy has been defined as a system of government involving all eligible members of a state, typically through elected representatives (Soanes & Stevenson, 2003). In this sense, Louis (2003:94-95) identifies three dominant paradigms of democratic societies: liberal, social and participatory democracy. In liberal democracies, the purpose of society is to benefit the individuals' development. Public education is prioritised, as the polity's responsibility is to support the individual in becoming autonomous.

Social democracy emphasises social rights and equality and is identified with welfare states such as the Scandinavian Countries (Louis, 2003). Emphasis is on group cohesiveness and the importance of redistributing social goods, including education (Møller, 2009). Protection of vulnerable classes of students is stressed. Møller adds distinguishing features of these countries' model of education include equity, participation and a welfare state. This resonates with South Africa's citizenship education, that aims to foster patriotism for obligation, solidarity, citizenship and flourishing by focusing on equity, social justice and diversity (Horstemke, Siyakwazi, Walton & Wolhuter, 2013).

Participatory democracy presumes participation and ownership, based on the Greek ideal of citizenship (Louis, 2003). Here, schools 'belong' to an identified local community, which is responsible for determining purpose and process. Most developed countries share in the conversations reflected by the three models. Du Toit and Forlin (2009) extol inclusive education as the gateway to a democratic and just society, and schools should promote this by inculcating inclusive values. Inclusive education (Engelbrecht, 2006) is in harmony with a democracy that values human dignity, freedom and equality.

Louis (2003) reiterates that, regardless of how distinctive these philosophies are on paper, the situation is different in practice, as every demo-cratic system contains its own contradictions between beliefs and actions. However, her argu-ment suggests that the adoption of democratic policies into contexts where cultural practices do not conform to democratic ideals can cause tension. This applies to Kenya, and many developing countries such as South Africa, whose 'democratic' political systems have been adopted from the developed countries into a context that Kabeberi (2007) considers unfavourable culturally, socially and economically.

Democratic school leadership

Democracy in schools is viewed as a form of social living, where individuals live and conduct their affairs within a sense of belonging to a community exercising mutual care for its members (Starratt, 2004). Essentially, democratic school leadership focuses on the cultivation of an environment that supports participation, sharing of ideas, honesty, openness, flexibility, and compassion. School lead-ers, therefore, should employ participatory app-roaches and ethics of social justice through structures that enable student and teacher views to be included in the decision-making process.

Ngubane (2005) indicates that school-based decision-making requires quality leadership and participative management. This can be attained if school management boards are competent, have open communication, build on trust and honesty and a shared vision and values, collective responsibility, reflective professional inquiry and collaboration (Owen, 2005).

Ethical rationality and democratic school leadership

Ethical rationality aims to create an environment in which people are encouraged and supported in aspiring to 'truths' about the world (Woods, GJ & Woods, 2008). They observe that the expression and reinforcement of a commitment to an as-piration to 'truth', which PA Woods (2006:331) refers to as "the kernel of ethical rationality", are integral to the development of human potential. Hence, one of the functions of leadership in a democratic school is to "engage people in processes that cause them to construct new knowledge" (Woods, PA 2006:331). PA Woods emphasises that a principal of a democratically managed school explains the importance of the collaborative approach, in terms of finding the right way and the best ideas.

PA Woods' ethical rationality relates to Starratt's (1991) ethic of critique, ethic of justice and ethic of care, each of which complements the others in a developmental context of practice. Similarly, Begley and Zaretsky (2004:641) contend that "our rational professional justifications for democratic leadership in schools are grounded in the nature of the school leadership role, the social contexts of the communities, as well as an ideological social mandate." The payoff to this form of leadership occurs when understanding the value orientations of others provide leaders with information on how they might best influence the practices of others towards the achievement of broadly justifiable social objectives. Stefkovich and Begley (2007) emphasise building consensus around a shared social objective in schools.

Møller (2006) identifies an ethic of care and a concern for the common good as elements of democratic school leadership. The ethic of care seeks to establish whether the students feel that the teachers trust them and express a caring attitude towards them. It encourages teachers and students to accept one another for who they are, and requires the principal to have open communication with the teachers regarding their welfare and school activities. Social events organised to develop oneness among members of the school community are key. This suggests that care and teamwork are crucial ingredients in democratic school leadership. Sam-uel and Van Wyk (2008:138) on a teachers' roles categorise them as "within classroom roles", such as being a "learning mediator", an "assessor" and a "designer of learning programmes", as well as "outside-of-classroom roles", such as being "a researcher", "a lifelong learner", and a "community practitioner executing pastoral roles." They re-iterate that policy makers recognise the need to appreciate the social, cultural and political role of schooling as follows:

"Teaching does not occur in a vacuum of specific contexts, where the dynamics of particular groups of learners, physical and financial resources predispose the teacher to make strategic choices linked to the specific environment and the ethos of the school culture which is driven by its own internal standards, especially around matters of diversity" (Samuel &Van Wyk, 2008:138).

Schooling is therefore a situated and an interpretative act, and ethical rationality enables participation by all striving towards human pro-gress and good values.

Social justice and democratic school leadership

Social justice is promoted by engendering respect for diversity and reducing cultural and material inequalities (Woods, GJ & Woods, 2008). This entails a collective obligation, which enables everyone to participate and work towards fulfilling their human potential. Social justice constitute the fair and just distribution of resources, respect and opportunities, as well as the eradication of social patterns of exploitation, domination and denigration (Woods, PA 2005).

Schooling, according to Shields and Mohan (2008), is meant to help students achieve individual success and employment and form the basis of a robust civil society, thus, schools must provide safe spaces and an education that promotes equity and social justice. They contend that educators cannot ignore the multiple forms of social, cultural and economic capital their students bring into their schools, and must take steps to provide an edu-cation that challenges and overcomes inequities. They assert that teachers can and should develop pedagogical understandings that make the class-room inclusive, equitable, and democratic.

Questions abound on what constitutes social justice. Johnson (2008:311) contends that post-modern concerns reject claims of a universal definition of social justice. They however, seek to identify and describe the multiple meanings of social justice at play in the collective and the power differentials perpetuated. Postmodernists therefore question any enactments of social justice from the perspective of the 'advantaged.' Interpretivists con-cur, identifying points of convergence between members of the collective. They attempt to enhance the stability of the collective by moving toward a consensual definition of social justice encouraging a culture of dialogue. Despite the varied para-digmatic views, Shields and Mohan (2008) em-phasise that consideration of students' lived ex-periences will enable teachers to understand stu-dents' varied socio-economic backgrounds. This knowledge is fundamental in enabling teachers provide all students with appropriate instruction and equitable learning opportunities based on individual needs.

Research Questions

In the context of this paper, it was essential to raise questions such as:

  • What do the principals, teachers and students consider as democracy, social justice and ethics in the learning/working environment?
  • How do the principals, teachers and students ensure democracy, social justice and ethics in the learning/working environment?

Conceptual Framework

The paper adopted the developmental conception of democratic practice and the elements of democratic school leadership in practice as a conceptual lens (Fielding, 2007; Woods, GJ & Woods, 2008; Woods, PA 2006). GJ Woods and Woods (2008) and PA Woods (2006) argue that a developmental conception of democratic practice is broader than the view of democracy and democratic school leadership as mere voting regularly for leaders, and is the model most relevant to education.

PA Woods further summarises the model into six interlinking aims (rationalities), namely: human potential (presupposes that each individual has untapped potential which can be brought to bear in the decision making process); ethical rationality (aims to create an environment in which people are encouraged and supported in aspiring to 'truths' about the world); decisional rationality (aims to disperse decision-making so that individuals are active contributors to the creation of the in-stitutions, culture and relationships they inhabit); therapeutic rationality (concerns the creation of well-being, social cohesion and positive feelings of involvement through participation and shared lead-ership); and discursive rationality, based on dia-logue and discussion, as well as "open debate and the operation of dialogic and deliberative dem-ocracy" (Woods, PA 2006:323). Cook-Sather (2006) prefer to see it as a 'speak with' rather than a 'speak for' approach. Lastly, social justice (is fair and just distribution of resources, respect and opportunities, as well as the eradication of social patterns of exploitation, domination and denigration) (Woods, GJ & Woods, 2008; Woods, PA 2005, 2006). These rationalities, as PA Woods articulates, "analytically distinguish the complementary and interacting dimensions of democratic leadership and practice and have their own distinctive focus, priorities and consequences" (2006:328).

 

Methodology

The study was an ethnographic case study (Jeffrey & Troman, 2004) grounded in commitment to first-hand experience and exploration of school settings via participant observation. The data were collected in two phases. Phase One lasted three months, and the 12 school principals interviewed here formed a basis/rationale for the selection of the two case schools. The data from the 12 principals have not been used in this paper. P1 (Case One School) and P10 (Case Two School) were selected for the second phase of the study. P1 was selected because she considered her leadership practices democratic, while P10 was selected because, in her view, democratic leadership was not suitable for her school. Phase two lasted three months. It involved spending six weeks in a Case One School and another six weeks in a Case Two School, generating data using interviews, focus group discussion, informal conversations and obser-vations. P1 was a national secondary boarding girls' school (that admits students aged between 14 to 18 years of age from the whole country), with over 70 teachers, and about 800 students.

Interviews were conducted with the Principal and eight teachers, based on the willingness to be interviewed, and their availability. The sample included representation from each of the three management tiers in the school - senior, middle, and junior. The senior management team included: the principal, deputy principal, the director of studies and the chaplain. The middle team included: three out of eight heads of department (HODs), and two out of fifteen subject teachers. The junior team included three out of forty-three ordinary classroom teachers. The sample was in-tended to ensure that the three demographic parameters based on the seniority of the teachers were captured. Each interview lasted approximately one hour and was audio-recorded with the consent of the participants.

Informal conversations were held to explore issues that emerged from the observations, they occurred before or after the interviews and a research journal was used to note down the issues covered. They did not follow any specific pattern and were not tape-recorded. As Pole and Morrison (2003) observe, conversations are a major element in any kind of ethnography field research both as a source of data and as a method. Informal con-versations were held with a group of teachers or one teacher over general issues about education and in the process matters came up that were related to the study, in which case the matter was pursued and relevant points noted soon after the conversations. Another type involved seeking clarifications from the teachers/students over a phenomenon that was observed in the school. For example, in P1, a student led a sermon on a Wednesday morning in the school chapel attended by all the students, as well as the majority of the teachers. After the sermon, an informal conversation was held with the Chaplain to find out who organised the services, and how the students who led were picked.

The focus group discussions (FGDs) were held with the students from all forms (SA equivalent Grade 8 to 12) and prefects and took place during the same data gathering process of three months. Each form/grade held its FGD separately, with those in form one (Gr 8) being first and the prefects coming last. Thus, each group was relatively homogeneous in terms of power re-lations. This was because it would be easier to seek clarification on issues that emerge from the young-er students from the mature students and the prefects. The students were identified with the help of the teachers on duty.i The teacher asked the class prefect to randomly select students within the same class to attend the FGD. The teacher did not have knowledge of the specific issues that would be discussed, thus, the approach did not pose any threat to the credibility of the study. Each of the FGDs lasted approximately one hour, comprised 12-16 students, and were conducted after class (4pm-5pm). While the ideal FGD should comprise 5-8 people, some students decided to join the FGDs of their own volition and it would be rude to send them away. This was handled by reducing the discussion period. The initial data analysis was done before the next FGD to pick out emerging issues that could be followed up on in the next FGD. The sessions were audio-recorded after getting the relevant assent (since the students are boarders and come from all over the country, the consent from the school management was sufficient).

Observation has been characterised as the fundamental base of all research methods in social and behavioural sciences, and as the mainstay of ethnographic study (Atkinson & Hammersley, 2007; Hammersley, 2006). It is useful for ethno-graphy and case studies (Lichtman, 2006) because it occurs in settings that already exist, rather than in contrived settings. Atkinson and Hammersley (2007) emphasise that even studies that rely mainly on interviewing as a data collection technique employ observation to note body language and other gestural cues that lend meaning to the words of the persons being interviewed. In both case schools, observations involved going to each school every morning to evening (8am-5pm), from Monday to Friday, for six weeks. It focused on specific areas, such as the staffrooms, school assemblies, classrooms, as well as isolated functions e.g. church services, games and a school cultural day (Case One School). This gave the advantage of 'shadowing' teachers through normal life, witnessing first hand and in detail the events and practices of interest (Denscombe, 1998). These were regularly written down as brief notes of the observed phenomena. We also noted overheard comments, remarks and discussions by the teach-ers, for example, teachers commenting about discipline among students, and how they (teachers) handle such matters. Teacher picked on students to undertake specific duties within the school. Only the issues relevant to the study were noted down.

P10 was a district secondary girls' boarding school located in a rural area, with about 272 students drawn from the locality and 18 teachers. Six teachers and the Principal were interviewed. Unlike in P1, where all the teachers were teachers service commission (TSC)ii employees, seven teachers in P10 were board of governors (BoG)iii employees. The teachers were divided into senior and junior teachers, based on the positions they held in the school. The senior teachers interviewed were the deputy principal, one TSC employed head of department (HoD) and one BoG employed HoD. The junior teachers interviewed were two TSC and one BoG teacher. Each interview lasted approx-imately one hour, and was audio-recorded with the consent of the participants. Notes on informal conversations held with teachers on matters ob-served and relevant to the study, such as corporal punishment, admission of new students, and overcrowded classrooms, were taken. The FGDs comprised students in all forms/grades and the prefects. The students were identified with the help of the teacher on duty. Each FGD lasted approximately one hour (4pm-5pm), were con-ducted after classes, and were audio-recorded after obtaining the relevant assent. Observations were confined to the staffroom, school assembly, lessons and games. The fact that students from P10 came from the locality (within the administrative District) was important for the study, because the disparity between the two schools would help identify if this diversity would be a major factor influencing social justice, even if the curriculum were basically the same across the country.

Thematic analysis was used to categorise the data generated. The initial step involved 'open' coding, which entailed developing categories of information from the data by examining the transcripts and field notes or salient categories of information supported by the text, for example, students' voice, equity, justice etc. The next stage was 'axial' coding, which involved interconnecting the categories identified in open coding, relating this to central phenomenon from the database. The final stage, viz. 'selective' coding, involved build-ing a story that connected the categories (Creswell, 2013), and picking out extracts that best illustrated the themes, identifying complementary and con-trasting points of view from the various data sources. Anonymity and confidentiality were en-sured through coding of the data. For example, C1-T1 means Case One interview one and C2-FGD3 is Case Two focus group discussion three. All necessary ethical considerations were observed. Authenticity and trustworthiness of data collected was ensured through credibility, transferability, dependability, and conformability, in other words, a step by step description of the data generation process undertaken to eliminate personal bias (Yin, 2009). Eisenhart (2006:573) suggests credibility of a study can increase through the use of concepts from the literature, excerpts and direct quotes from the data sources, which he terms "having been there." Jwan and Ong'ondo (2011) concur, saying credibility can be assured by establishing 'a chain of evidence.' In this paper, a step-by-step description of the data generation process was provided, alongside excerpts and direct quotations.

 

Discussion

Teachers' Perception on Democracy, Ethics and Social Justice

Though the majority of teachers interviewed felt they treated one another with care and respect, they held contrasting views on the issue. One teacher in P1 argued that while there were those who treated her with respect, there were also those who did not. She stated that a few teachers exhibited care based on ethnic considerations. This, she claimed, had been heightened by the political division in the country at the time, as many Kenyans define their support for political parties through ethnic affili-ation. However, some teachers have stated that they treated one another with care and respect despite their political and ethnic affiliations:

"We relate quite well. Yes, we may have some 'camps' but they are not so pronounced because we try as much as possible to be one, but you can't rule out those 'camps.' I personally try not to be in any 'camp', but because of my name,iv people would just say this one is for this political party. You know that mentality" [senior teacher: C1-T7].

A teacher whose parent's home was burnt down during the 2007 post-election violence and who came from an ethnic community that was con-sidered 'foreign' in the school, explained that al-though she was treated with care and respect there were a lot of political undertones from colleagues:

"We do not have obvious divisions in the staff except when political debate is rife, we can have tea together and as much as I would want to participate, I'm very careful, because I belong to a minority ethnic community. However, when the 2008 conflict became so bad, several of my colleagues called me to find out if I was safe. I was also given a school-house [a staff house in the school compound], just in case I feel unsafe in my current residence [sic]. Although we have different political affiliations, we still care for one another" [Junior teacher: C1-T6].

Most of the teachers interviewed felt the Principal treated them with care and respect:

"We don't even refer to her with the title 'Principal', she is our mother. And, the way she relates with us is the same way a mother relates with the children, very understanding, very hu-mane. She is always ready to listen to us. She understands that this is a national school with students and teachers from all over this country" [Middle-level teacher: C1-T3].

The Principal concurred that she tried to make all the teachers feel welcome, cared for and respected:

"I don't know! You cannot rule out that there are people who prefer to work together, but we have not had any problem. I think people are free to oppose an issue [sic]. In fact, the people who give me hard time are usually the people I trust to work with. They say 'madam that is wrong' and we discuss until we agree. I also encourage them that when they have an issue, they should come and discuss it so that everybody is comfortable and promotions of teachers are always on merit" [Principal: C1-T9].

These views on ethnic affiliations were not surprising, because in Kenya, ethnic community cultures are stronger than the national culture, and people this is what people tend to build relationships based on this.

In P10, the teachers unanimously agreed that the principal treated them with care seen by the amount of time he spent with them in the staffroom. All teachers reiterated that they cared and respected one another regardless of their ethnic backgrounds. One teacher stated:

"We tend to help each other where there is need. We don't even know who is senior or junior, employed by the BoG or the TSC. And, we have a welfare association where we each contribute two hundred shillings a month to assist members when bereaved or blessed with a baby" [junior teacher: C2-T2].

The above excerpts indicate, the teachers viewed democracy, ethics and social justice as a cultural practice (from an African perspective) seeing it as fair treatment, respect and a sense of belonging. This resonates with Ngubane's (2005) view that trust, honesty, a shared vision and values are important elements of care. Similarly, Møller (2006) identifies an ethic of care and a concern for the common good as elements of democratic school leadership.

Students' Perception on Democracy, Ethics and Social Justice

In both schools most of the students felt that the principals treated them in a just and ethical manner. In P1, the students gave an instance when a student was hospitalised and the Principal allowed other students to visit her in hospital. The students viewed this as care and concern. In P10, most of the students felt the Principal exhibited care when dealing with them on school fees related matters.

The students' view is consistent with Stefkovich and Begley's (2007) argument that genuine regard for student's best interests is a major influence on principal leadership practices: principal's valuation processes are heavily oriented towards a concern for the students' well-being and their response when confronted with ethical dilemmas suggests that the best interests of students feature prominently as the ultimate influence on these administrators' decision making.

In P10, the teachers viewed the provision of school uniform and the requirement that all students keep short hair as a sign of equality:

We make sure that all students are equal by the form of dressing i.e. the school provides their uniform, once they are all in uniform, they are all equal. We also ensure that all the girls keep short hair [senior teacher: C2-T6].

The care was also extended to new students in the school. In an informal conversation with one teacher (C2-T5), she explained that they had a case where an orphaned student could not raise money to buy her requirements. The Principal, the teachers and students raised money for all her requirements and "the other students are treating her so well her background not withstanding" [Junior: C2-T5]. GJ Woods and Woods (2008) claim ethical rationality invokes commitment to truth and appreciation of positive human potential. This entails self-reflection, open-mindedness and an understanding that this profoundly influences students' lives (Stefkovich & Begley, 2007).

However, in both case schools, some students maintained that some teachers did not treat them fairly. For example teachers who gossiped and made negative comments on students in class (cf. p. 4). Teachers did not seem to be aware of the students' feelings towards them regarding favouritism and gossip, however, Strømstad (2003) argues, teachers should develop and create a climate of democratic culture and tolerance. Social justice entails fairness and respect.

Academic Families

This was a system used in P10 to give students an informal forum to express themselves and discuss personal matters with teachers:

The Principal involves us a lot in management, she has helped us to form families with students, and every teacher is assigned a number of girls. We meet every two weeks to discuss varied problems [sic] both academic and non-academic. It helps improve on discipline. We warn them that 'I don't want to see my children in the staffroom being punished' [junior teacher: C2-T5].

Most students concurred that the family system enhanced teachers' care for them:

Yes, I believe that teachers have a caring attitude towards students because like now we have been grouped and given teachers to act as our parents. We usually have meetings on Thursday and we are free to tell them any problem we have and get assistance [student: C2-FGD1].

However, the observations indicated, the family meetings lacked the personal engagement mentioned above as the discussions appeared to focus on formal matters such as career choices. In one of the 'family' meeting days, the Principal asked the teachers to go and discuss career choices, in another, she asked the teachers to discuss "grooming and neatness for girls and how to relate with boys." One teacher explained that if there was a topic that needed to be discussed with the students, e.g. sexuality, then the teachers would read on the topic and they would discuss in the staffroom and agree on how to present it to the students. Nevertheless, the importance of such forums is highlighted by Mitra (2006) in a study conducted in three schools in San Francisco designed to find 'best case' scenarios of student voice efforts. She points out that student forums (student-focused activities) were intended to help teachers to gain a better understanding of student perspectives. Overall, the forums were meant to help reduce tension and increase informality between teachers and students.

Care and Respect among Students

Students in both schools had contrasting views on care and respect, some regarded it as an absence from bullying, others as respecting someone's personal belongings, others as one's socio-economic background and equal treatment for all. Stefkovich and Begley (2007) assert that while having rights is a manifestation of equal respect, balancing the claims of other and self, responsibility rests on an understanding that gives rise to compassion and care. Thus, responsibility is an important component of the ethic of care. For students to be treated with care and respect, they too must reciprocate. One teacher [C1-T6] commented that some students cared for one another, depending on their socio-economic background.

To facilitate care among students, the teachers organised induction conferences for new students to instil the virtue of care and respect and allocated them school mums.v

Equal Care for All Students

The teachers in both schools asserted that they treated all the students equally. They drew attention to the school uniform and the fact that students were not allowed to have more than one thousand Kenya shillings (about R700) in the school. In P10, all the girls kept short hair whilst in P1 they were allowed to keep long hair but not use 'chemicals' relaxers. The irony in the teachers' claims is that while they believed they were trying to make the students appear equal, they did not realise they were denying them the right of 'choice'. Shields and Mohan (2008) argue that although social justice may not 'make up' for the disadvantages experienced by some students, it is still the only meaningful way to address the needs of disparate student groups by creating a more equitable playing field. However, this argument raises a potential tension between the school culture and the students' cultural background because creating a learning environment that reflects the background of one group may in a way disadvantage another group. They add that it is central to an educator's ability to create learning environments in which all children experience success, can become curious, inquiring and critically reflective.

Some students commented that the teachers tended to care more for those who performed well in their subjects: Excerpt from a student in P10:

I think teachers don't treat us equally. Some teachers care more for those who pass well in their subjects. And our parents are also treated differently. For example, when my parent comes to the school riding a bicycle or walking and my friend's parent comes driving a Toyota Prado [sic]. The teacher will tend to recognise the one in a Prado [sic] which is unfair [student: C2-FGD2].

A similar view was expressed by a student in P1:

Our Business teacher seems to like the students who do well in the subject and ignore those who do not perform very well. For example, if you do not perform well in the subject and you are not in class the teacher will not bother asking, but for some students, the teacher will always ask where the student is [student: C1- FGD3].

Principals' Perceptions on Democracy, Ethics and Social Justice

Both principals indicated that they relied on trial and error as their college training prepared them for roles as classroom teachers and not for the kind of democratic school leadership expected of them when they became principals, P1 states:

I used coercion and persuasion to run the school. Earlier on, it was okay for a principal to run the school without involving others. But that is now outdated. The principal of today is not the sole decision-maker. She is the coordinator in the new management arrangement. So, now I encourage teachers to be more democratic when dealing with students. We need to consult the students and get ideas on what they need. Students have good ideas on how to be taught, how to manage themselves. We now ask students about their meals and the way it should be cooked, which was never the case before [P1].

P1 further explained that the school culture was instrumental, they had developed a strategic plan, vision, mission, motto, school anthem and school rules every teacher and student who joined the school was inducted in the ideals and values of the school through a week long induction programme. Another issue raised by P1 was equal treatment of all students based on religious principles of Christianity/Islam, thus religion served as an agent of enhancing school culture. Lastly she indicated that teachers were involved in the school structure through various committees such as financial management, guidance and counselling, disciplinary, academic boards, games. This facilitated democratic school leadership because it made clear the roles of each group of teachers in a committee preventing duplication of roles. It also helped students know where their concerns could be addressed.

Both principals bemoaned the lack of clear guidelines on how to practice democratic school leadership. P10 reiterated her stance that democratic school leadership was not suitable for her school as

I have tried holding barazas [Swahili word for informal public meetings] like two weeks ago I had a baraza with the form four students to get their views on what they needed. At class level democracy may work but at times the students want to blame the teachers, the administration and this interferes with the working atmosphere because the teachers get offended [P10].

She gave an example where the Government insisted that principals charge school fees based on 1997 fee guidelines despite current inflation rates. She reiterated that the government lauds involvement of stakeholders in decision making yet the Ministry of Education rarely involved principals in the decision they make that affect schools "preaching water and drinking wine." Samuel and Van Wyk (2008) contend a school culture/ethos, driven by a schools' internal standards, such as diversity concerns are fundamental.

Limitations

The case study while not allowing for statistical generalization, can allow for analytical generalisation (Yin, 2009). Nevertheless, involving more schools may have provided more insights to the study considering the diverse and distinct socio-cultural orientations of the many ethnic communities in Kenya. However, this being a qualitative study, the empirical evidence generated may contribute to our understanding of the views held and application of democracy, ethics and social justice in these specific schools and not necessarily to make wider claims to generalisation. The two case schools represent schools in Kenya which are either national or district schools and the issues raised may resonate with other schools in Kenya with similar characteristics.

Educational Implications

Democratic school leadership was practised in both schools, however, there were instances when it was not evident. This can compromise learning as inclusive classroom environments require educators to clearly distinguish between students' ability versus their opportunity to learn (Shields & Mohan, 2008). We concur with this view that consideration of students' lived experiences will help teachers and principals to understand and differentiate students' needs striving to provide all with equitable learning opportunities.

The perceptions of democratic school leadership did not vary much between the two case schools and appeared confined to participation in decision-making and the rights of students and teachers to express their views freely. However, a lot of practices within the schools can be considered democratic.

Principals' cited lack of guidelines on implementing the government policy. The principals' teachers' and students' 'rational' perceptions of democratic school leadership (which were not significantly different from the elements of democracy discussed in literature) did not appear to inform their practices rather the 'culturally embedded' perceptions, influenced their school practices. This is contrary to the stated national goals of education. These contrasting views call for further discourse on the phenomenon. We recommend:

  • A recognition of the cultural conception of democracy, ethics and social justice in school practices;
  • Formal training for principals through in-service courses on democratic school leadership, ethics and social justice;
  • School ethos that inculcate democracy, ethics and social justice.

 

Notes

i. In Kenya, a teacher who is in charge of school programmes for the week is commonly referred to as "The Teacher on Duty."
ii. In Kenya a TSC teacher is a teacher employed by the Teachers Service Commission (equivalent to the Department of Basic Education (DBE) and is a permanent employee.
iii. A BoG teacher is a teacher employed by the Board of Governors (similar to the School governing board-SGB) and is usually a contractual appointment.
iv. In Kenya, one's ethnicity can be identified from their surname because some ethnic communities have names unique to them.
v. A school mum is where a senior student (grade 9) is assigned to a new student (grade 8) as a mother to teach them the ropes of settling into life in boarding school.
vi. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution Licence.

 

References

Atkinson P & Hammersley M 2007. Ethnography: principles in practice (3rd ed). London, UK: Routledge.         [ Links ]

Begley PT & Zaretsky L 2004. Democratic school leadership in Canada's public school systems: professional value and social ethic. Journal of Educational Administration, 42(6):640-655. https://doi.org/10.1108/09578230410563647        [ Links ]

Cook-Sather A 2006. 'Change based on what students say': preparing teachers for a paradoxical model of leadership. International Journal of Leadership in Educational, 9(4):345-358. https://doi.org/10.1080/13603120600895437        [ Links ]

Creswell JW 2013. Qualitative inquiry & research design: Choosing among five approaches (3rd ed). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc.         [ Links ]

Denscombe M 1998. The good research guide for small-scale research projects. Berkshire, England: Open University Press.         [ Links ]

Du Toit P & Forlin C 2009. Cultural transformation for inclusion, what is needed?: A South African perspective. School Psychology International, 30(6):644-666. https://doi.org/10.1177/0143034309107081        [ Links ]

Eisenhart M 2006. Representing qualitative data. In JL Green, G Camilli & PB Elmore (eds). Handbook of complementary methods in education research. London, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Publishers.         [ Links ]

Engelbrecht P 2006. The implementation of inclusive education in South Africa after ten years of democracy. European Journal of Psychology of Education, 21:253. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03173414        [ Links ]

Fielding M 2007. On the necessity of radical state education: Democracy and the common school. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 41(4):539-557. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.2007.00593.x        [ Links ]

Hammersley M 2006. Ethnography: problems and prospects. Ethnography and Education, 1(1):3-14. https://doi.org/10.1080/17457820500512697        [ Links ]

Horstemke K, Siyakwazi P, Walton E & Wolhuter C (eds.) 2013. Education studies: History, sociology, philosophy. Cape Town, South Africa: Oxford University Press.         [ Links ]

Jeffrey B & Troman G 2004. Time for ethnography. British Educational Research Journal, 30(4):535-548. https://doi.org/10.1080/0141192042000237220        [ Links ]

Johnson BL Jr. 2008. Exploring multiple meanings and pursuits of social justice: a reflection on modern, interpretive, and postmodern possibilities. Teacher Development, 12(4):301-318. https://doi.org/10.1080/13664530802579868        [ Links ]

Jwan OJ & Ong'ondo CO 2011. Qualitative research: An introduction to principles and techniques. Eldoret, Kenya: Moi University Press.         [ Links ]

Kabeberi N 2007. Political culture and the prospects of multi-party democracy in Kenya: Lessons learnt from the Centre for Multiparty Democracy-Kenya (CMD-Kenya). In K Njogu & G Oluoch-Olunya (eds). Cultural production and social change in Kenya: Building bridges. Nairobi, Kenya: Twaweza Communications Ltd.         [ Links ]

Lichtman M 2006. Qualitative research in education: A user's guide. London, UK: Sage Publications Ltd.         [ Links ]

Louis KS 2003. Democratic schools, democratic communities: Reflections in an international context. Leadership and Policy in Schools, 2(2):93-108.         [ Links ]

Mitra DL 2006. Student voice from the inside and outside: the positioning of challengers. International Journal of Leadership in Educational, 9(4):315-328. https://doi.org/10.1080/13603120600895379        [ Links ]

Møller J 2006. Democratic schooling in Norway: Implications for leadership in practice. Leadership and Policy in Schools, 5(1):53-69. https://doi.org/10.1080/15700760500498779        [ Links ]

Møller J 2009. Approaches to school leadership in Scandinavia. Journal of Educational Administration and History, 41(2):165-177. https://doi.org/10.1080/00220620902808244        [ Links ]

Ngubane WS 2005. An investigation into the implementation of participative management in a rural school in the Pietermaritzburg district. MEd dissertation. Grahamstown, South Africa: Rhodes University.         [ Links ]

Owen SS 2005. The relationship between social capital and corporal punishments in schools: A theoretical inquiry. Youth & Society, 37(1):85-112. https://doi.org/10.1177/0044118X04271027        [ Links ]

Pole C & Morrison M 2003. Ethnography for education. Berkshire, England: Open University Press.         [ Links ]

Republic of Kenya 1964. Kenya education commission report. Nairobi, Kenya: Government Printers.         [ Links ]

Samuel M & Van Wyk M 2008. Narratives of professional development: Forces in the field. Education as Change, 12(2):137-153. https://doi.org/10.1080/16823200809487212        [ Links ]

Shields CM & Mohan EJ 2008. High-quality education for all students: putting social justice at its heart. Teacher Development, 12(4):289-300. https://doi.org/10.1080/13664530802579843        [ Links ]

Soanes C & Stevenson A (eds.) 2003. Oxford Dictionary of English (2nd ed). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.         [ Links ]

Starratt RJ 1991. Building an ethical school: A theory for practice in educational leadership. Educational Administration Quarterly, 27(2):185-202. https://doi.org/10.1177/0013161X91027002005        [ Links ]

Starratt RJ 2004. Leadership of the contested terrain of education for democracy. Journal of Education Administration, 42(6):724-731. https://doi.org/10.1108/09578230410563700        [ Links ]

Stefkovich J & Begley PT 2007. Ethical school leadership: Defining the best interests of students. Educational Management Administration & Leadership, 35(2):205-224. https://doi.org/10.1177/1741143207075389        [ Links ]

Strømstad M 2003. 'They believe that they participate … but': Democracy and inclusion in Norwegian schools. In J Allan (ed). Inclusion, participation and democracy: What is the purpose? (Vol. 2). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.         [ Links ]

Woods GJ & Woods PA 2008. Democracy and spiritual awareness: interconnections and implications for educational leadership. International Journal of Children's Spirituality, 13(2):101-116. https://doi.org/10.1080/13644360801965891        [ Links ]

Woods PA 2005. Democratic leadership in education. London, UK: Paul Chapman Publishing.         [ Links ]

Woods PA 2006. A democracy of all learners: ethical rationality and the affective roots of democratic leadership. School Leadership & Management, 26(4):321-337. https://doi.org/10.1080/13632430600900672        [ Links ]

Woods PA & Gronn P 2009. Nurturing democracy: The contribution of distributed leadership to a democratic organizational landscape. Educational Management Administration & Leadership, 37(4):430-451. https://doi.org/10.1177/1741143209334597        [ Links ]

Yin RK 2009. Case study research: Design and methods (4th ed). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc.         [ Links ]

1. The Concept of Autonomy

In the western tradition, the view that individual autonomy is a basic moral and political value is very much a modern development. Putting moral weight on an individual's ability to govern herself, independent of her place in a metaphysical order or her role in social structures and political institutions is very much the product of the modernist humanism of which much contemporary moral and political philosophy is an offshoot. (For historical discussions of autonomy, see Schneewind 1988, Lindley 1986, Part I). As such, it bears the weight of the controversies that this legacy has attracted. The idea that moral principles and obligations, as well as the legitimacy of political authority, should be grounded in the self-governing individual, considered apart from various contingencies of place, culture, and social relations, invites skeptics from several quarters. Autonomy, then, is very much at the vortex of the complex (re)consideration of modernity.

Put most simply, to be autonomous is to be one's own person, to be directed by considerations, desires, conditions, and characteristics that are not simply imposed externally upon one, but are part of what can somehow be considered one's authentic self. Autonomy in this sense seems an irrefutable value, especially since its opposite — being guided by forces external to the self and which one cannot authentically embrace — seems to mark the height of oppression. But specifying more precisely the conditions of autonomy inevitably sparks controversy and invites skepticism about the claim that autonomy is an unqualified value for all individuals.

Autonomy plays various roles in theoretical accounts of persons, conceptions of moral obligation and responsibility, the justification of social policies and in numerous aspects of political theory. It forms the core of the Kantian conception of practical reason (see, e.g, Korsgaard 1996, Hill 1989) and, relatedly, connects to questions of moral responsibility (see Wolff 1970, 12–19). It is also seen as the aspect of persons that prevents or ought to prevent paternalistic interventions in their lives (Dworkin 1988, 121–29). It plays a role in education theory and policy, on some views specifying the core goal of liberal education generally (Gutmann 1987, Cuypers and Haji 2008; for discussion, see Brighouse 2000, 65–111). Also, despite many feminists' reservations concerning the ideal of autonomy, it is sometimes seen as a valuable conceptual element in some feminist ideals, such as the identification and elimination of social conditions that victimize women and other (potentially) vulnerable people (Friedman 1997, Meyers 1987, Christman 1995).

1.1 Basic Distinctions

Several distinctions must be made to zero in on the kind of autonomy that is of greatest interest to moral and political theory. “Moral autonomy” refers to the capacity to impose the (putatively objective) moral law on oneself, and, following Kant, it is claimed as a fundamental organizing principle of all morality (Hill 1989). On the other hand, what can be called “personal autonomy” is meant as a trait that individuals can exhibit relative to any aspects of their lives, not limited to questions of moral obligation (Dworkin 1988, 34–47).

Personal (or individual) autonomy should also be distinguished from freedom, although again, there are many renderings of these concepts, and certainly some conceptions of positive freedom will be equivalent to what is often meant by autonomy (Berlin 1969, 131–34). Generally, one can distinguish autonomy from freedom in that the latter concerns the ability to act, without external or internal constraints and also (on some conceptions) with sufficient resources and power to make one's desires effective (Berlin 1969, Crocker 1980, MacCallum 1967). Autonomy concerns the independence and authenticity of the desires (values, emotions, etc.) that move one to act in the first place. Some distinguish autonomy from freedom by insisting that freedom concerns particular acts while autonomy is a more global notion, referring to states of a person (Dworkin 1988, 13–15, 19–20). But autonomy can be used to refer both to the global condition (autonomous personhood) and as a more local notion (autonomous relative to a particular trait, motive, value, or social condition). Addicted smokers for example are autonomous persons in a general sense but (for some) helplessly unable to control their behavior regarding this one activity (Christman 1989, 13–14).

In addition, we must keep separate the idea of basic autonomy, the minimal status of being responsible, independent and able to speak for oneself, from ideal autonomy, an achievement that serves as a goal to which we might aspire and according to which a person is maximally authentic and free of manipulative, self-distorting influences. Any plausible conceptualization of basic autonomy must, among other things, imply that most adults who are not suffering from debilitating pathologies or are under oppressive and constricting conditions count as autonomous. Autonomy as an ideal, on the other hand, may well be enjoyed by very few if any individuals, for it functions as a goal to be attained.

The reason to construe basic autonomy broadly enough to include most adults is that autonomy connects with other status designators which apply (or, it is claimed, should apply) in this sweeping manner. Autonomy is connected, for example, to moral and legal responsibility, on some views (e.g., Ripstein 1999); it is considered a criterion of political status, in that autonomous agency is seen as necessary (and for some sufficient) for the condition of equal political standing; moreover, being autonomous stands as a barrier to unchecked paternalism, both in the personal, informal spheres and in legal arenas (Feinberg 1986). Lacking autonomy, as young children do, is a condition which allows or invites sympathy, care, paternalism and possibly pity. Therefore, a guiding consideration in evaluating particular conceptions of autonomy (though hardly a hard and fast test) will be whether it connects properly to these ancillary judgments (for discussion of “formal conditions” of a concept of autonomy, see Dworkin 1988, 7–10).

1.2 Conceptual Variations

The variety of contexts in which the concept of autonomy functions has suggested to many that there are simply a number of different conceptions, and that the word simply refers to different elements in each of those contexts (Arpaly 2004). Feinberg has claimed that there are at least four different meanings of “autonomy” in moral and political philosophy: the capacity to govern oneself, the actual condition of self-government, a personal ideal, and a set of rights expressive of one's sovereignty over oneself (Feinberg 1989). One might argue that central to all of these uses is a conception of the person able to act, reflect, and choose on the basis of factors that are somehow her own (authentic in some sense). Nevertheless, it is clear that formulating a “theory” of the concept will involve more than merely uncovering the obscure details of the idea's essence, for autonomy, like many concepts central to contentious moral or political debate is itself essentially contested. So a theory of autonomy is simply a construction of a concept aimed at capturing the general sense of “self-rule” or “self-government” (ideas which obviously admit of their own vagaries) and which can be used to support principles or policies the theory attempts to justify.

The idea of self-rule contains two components: the independence of one's deliberation and choice from manipulation by others, and the capacity to rule oneself (see Dworkin 1989, 61f and Arneson 1991). However, the ability to rule oneself will lie at the core of the concept, since a full account of that capability will surely entail the freedom from external manipulation characteristic of independence. Indeed, it could be claimed that independence per se has no fixed meaning or necessary connection with self-government unless we know what kinds of independence is required for self-rule (cf., however Raz 1986, 373-78).

Focusing, then, on the requirements of self rule, it can be claimed that to govern oneself one must be in a position to act competently based on desires (values, conditions, etc.) that are in some sense one's own. This picks out the two families of conditions often proffered in conceptions of autonomy: competency conditions and authenticity conditions. Competency includes various capacities for rational thought, self-control, and freedom from debilitating pathologies, systematic self-deception, and so on. (Different accounts include different conditions: see, for example, Berofsky 1995, R. Young 1991, Haworth 1986, Meyers 1989.)

Authenticity conditions often include the capacity to reflect upon and endorse (or identify with) one's desires, values, and so on. The most influential models of authenticity in this vein claim that autonomy requires second-order identification with first order desires. For Frankfurt, for instance, such second-order desires must actually have the structure of a volition: wanting that the first order desires issue in action, that they comprise one's will. Moreover, such identification, on his view, must be “wholehearted” for the resulting action to count as free (autonomous).[1]

This overall approach to autonomy has been very influential, and several writers have developed variations of it and defended it against objections. The most prominent objections concern, on the one hand, the fatal ambiguities of the concept of “identification” and, on the other, the threat of an infinite regress of conditions. The first problem surrounds the different ways that one can be said to “identify” with a desire, each of which render the view conceptually suspect. Either one identifies with an aspect of oneself in the sense of simply acknowledging it (without judgment) or one identifies with a desire in an aspirational, approving sense of that term. In the first case, however, identification would clearly not be a consistent mark of autonomy, for one could easily identify as part of oneself any manner of addictive, constricting, or imposed aspects of one's make-up. But approving of a trait is also problematic as a requirement of autonomy, for there are many perfectly authentic aspects of myself (ones for which I can and should be held fully responsible for example) which I do not fully approve of. I'm not perfect, but does that mean that I am thereby not autonomous? (Cf. Watson 1989, Berofsky 1995, 99–102).[2]

This model stresses internal self-reflection and procedural independence. However, the view includes no stipulations about the content of the desires, values, and so on, in virtue of which one is considered autonomous, specifically there is no requirement that one act from desires independently of others. Were there to be such a requirement, it would involve what is called “substantive independence”. Some writers have insisted that the autonomous person must enjoy substantive independence as well as procedural independence (e.g., Stoljar 2000, Benson 1987, 2005, Oshana 2006). The motivation for such a position is that autonomy should not be understood as consistent with certain constrained life situations no matter how the person came to choose such a situation (cf. Meyers 2000). This claim, however, threatens to rob the attribution of autonomy of any claim to value neutrality it may otherwise carry, for if, conceptually, one is not autonomous when one (freely, rationally, without manipulation) chooses to enter conditions of severely limited choice, then the concept is reserved to only those lifestyles and value pursuits that are seen as acceptable from a particular political or theoretical point of view. I will return to this line of thought in a moment.

One variation on the internal self-reflection model focuses on the importance of the personal history of the agent as an element of her autonomy (Christman 1991, Mele 1993; cf. Fisher & Ravizza 1998; cf. also Raz 1986, 371). On these views, the question of whether a person is autonomous at a time depends on the processes by which she came to be the way she is. It is not clear that such a focus will be able to avoid the problems raised about internal reflection models (see Mele 1991, Mackenzie & Stoljar 2000b, 16–17), but such a move attempts to embrace a conception of the self of self-government which is not only social but diachronically structured (see, e.g., Atkins 2008, Cuypers 2001).

For those who are wary of the postulate of reflective self endorsement, an alternative approach is to equate autonomy with simply a set of competences, such as the capacity to choose deliberatively, rationally, and, as Berofsky claims, “objectively” (see Berofsky 1995, Meyers 1989). This locates autonomy in the general capacity to respond to reasons, and not, for example, in acts of internal self-identification. However, even in these accounts, the capacity to think critically and reflectively is necessary for autonomy as one of the competences in question, even though the reflective thought required need not refer to external values or ideals (Berofsky 1995, ch. 5).

Further difficulties have been raised with the requirement of second order self-appraisal for autonomy. For it is unclear that such higher level judgments have any greater claim to authenticity than their first order cousins. Clearly if a person is manipulated or oppressed (and hence non-autonomous), it could well be that the reflective judgments she makes about herself are just as tainted by that oppression as are her ground-level decisions (Thalberg 1989, Friedman 1986, Meyers 1989, 25–41, Noggle 2005), and often our second order reflective voices are merely rationalizations and acts of self-deception rather than true and settled aspects of our character (for general discussion see the essays in Veltman and Piper 2014). This has led to the charge that models of autonomy which demand second-order endorsement merely introduce an infinite regress: for second-level judgments must be tested for their authenticity in the same way as first order desires are, but if that is so, then ever higher levels of endorsement would be called for. Various responses to this problem have been made, for the most part involving the addition of conditions concerning the manner in which such reflection must be made, for example that it must be free of certain distorting factors itself, it must reflect an adequate causal history, and the like (Christman 1991, Mele 1995).

Other aspects of the inner reflection model should be noted. As just mentioned, this view of autonomy is often stated as requiring critical self reflection (see, e.g., Haworth 1986). This has been understood as involving a rational appraisal of one's desires, testing them for internal consistency, their relation to reliable beliefs, and the like. But an overly narrow concentration on rational assessment exposes such conceptions to charges of hyper intellectualism, painting a picture of the autonomous person as a cold, detached calculator (see Meyers 2004, 111–37). Connections to values, desires, and personal traits are often grounded in emotional and affective responses, ones connected with care, commitment, and relations to others (see Friedman 1998, MacKenzie & Stoljar 2000b, Meyers 1989). For parallel reasons, some theorists have noted that concentration on only desires as the focal point of autonomy is overly narrow, as people can (fail to) exhibit self-government relative to a wide range of personal characteristics, such as values, physical traits, relations to others, and so on (see Double 1992, 66).

2. Autonomy in Moral Philosophy

Autonomy is central in certain moral frameworks, both as a model of the moral person — the feature of the person by virtue of which she is morally obligated — and as the aspect of persons which ground others' obligations to her or him. For Kant, the self-imposition of universal moral law is the ground of both moral obligation generally and the respect others owe to us (and we owe ourselves). In short, practical reason — our ability to use reasons to choose our own actions — presupposes that we understand ourselves as free. Freedom means lacking barriers to our action that are in any way external to our will, though it also requires that we utilize a law to guide our decisions, a law that can come to us only by an act of our own will (for further discussion see Hill 1989). This self-imposition of the moral law is autonomy. And since this law must have no content provided by sense or desire, or any other contingent aspect of our situation, it must be universal. Hence we have the (first formulation of the) Categorical Imperative, that by virtue of our being autonomous we must act only on those maxims that we can consistently will as a universal law.

The story continues, however: for the claim is that this capacity (to impose upon ourselves the moral law) is the ultimate source of all moral value — for to value anything (instrumentally or intrinsically) implies the ability to make value judgments generally, the most fundamental of which is the determination of what is morally valuable. Some theorists who are not (self-described) Kantians have made this inference central to their views of autonomy. Paul Benson, for example, has argued that being autonomous implies a measure of self-worth in that we must be in a position to trust our decision-making capacities to put ourselves in a position of responsibility (Benson 1994; cf. also Grovier 1993, Lehrer 1997, and Westlund 2014). But the Kantian position is that such self-regard is not a contingent psychological fact about us, but an unavoidable implication of the exercise of practical reason (cf. Taylor 2005).

So we owe to ourselves moral respect in virtue of our autonomy. But insofar as this capacity depends in no way on anything particular or contingent about ourselves, we owe similar respect to all other persons in virtue of their capacity. Hence (via the second formulation of the Categorical Imperative), we are obliged to act out of fundamental respect for other persons in virtue of their autonomy. In this way, autonomy serves as both a model of practical reason in the determination of moral obligation and as the feature of other persons deserving moral respect from us. (For further discussion, see Immanual Kant and moral philosophy.)

Recent discussions of Kantian autonomy have downplayed the transcendental nature of practical reason in this account (see, for example, Herman 1993 and Hill 1991). For example, Christine Korsgaard follows Kant in seeing our capacity for self-reflection as both the object of respect and the seat of normativity generally. On her view, we are all guided by what she calls a “practical identity”, a point of view which orients reflection on values and manifests an aspect of our self concept. But unlike Kant, Korsgaard argues that we have different practical identities that are the source of our normative commitments, and not all of them are of fundamental moral worth. But the most general of such identities — that which makes us members of a kingdom of ends — is our moral identity, which yields universal duties and obligations independent of contingent factors. Autonomy is the source of all obligations, whether moral or non-moral, since it is the capacity to impose upon ourselves, by virtue of our practical identities, obligations to act (Korsgaard 1996).

Traditional critiques of autonomy-based moral views, and Kant's in particular, have been mounted along various lines. I mention two here, as they connect with issues concerning autonomy in social and political theory. The first concerns the way in which autonomy-based moral theory grounds obligation in our cognitive abilities rather than in our emotions and affective connections (see, e.g., Williams 1985, Stocker 1976). The claim is that Kantian morality leaves too little room for the kinds of emotional reactions that are constitutive of moral response in many situations: the obligations of parents for example concern not only what they do but the passions and care they bring forth in doing it. To view obligation as arising from autonomy but understanding autonomy in a purely cognitive manner makes such an account vulnerable to this kind of charge.

The difficulty this criticism points to resides in the ambiguities of the self-description that we might utilize in valuing our “humanity” — our capacity to obligate ourselves. For we can reflect upon our decision-making capacities and value this positively (and fundamentally) but regard that “self” engaging the capacity in different ways. The Kantian model of such a self is of a pure cognizer — a reflective agent engaged in practical reason. But also involved in decision-making are our passions — emotions, desires, felt commitments, senses of attraction and aversion, alienation and comfort. These are both the objects of our judgement and partly constitutive of them — to passionately embrace an option is different from cooly determining it to be best. Judgment is involved with all such passions when decisions are made. And it (judgment) need not be understood apart from them, but as an ability to engage in those actions whose passionate and reasoned support we muster up. So when the optimal decision for me is an impassioned one, I must value my ability to engage in the right passions, not merely in the ability to cold-heartedly reflect and choose. Putting the passions outside the scope of reasoned reflection, as merely an ancillary quality of the action — to consider how to do something not merely what we are doing — is to make one kind of decision. Putting passions inside that scope — saying that what it is right to do now is to act with a certain affect or passion — is another. When we generalize from our ability to make the latter sort of decisions, we must value not only the ability to weigh options and universalize them but also the ability to engage the right affect, emotion, etc. Therefore, we value ourselves and others as passionate reasoners not merely reasoners per se.

The implications of this observation is that in generalizing our judgments in the manner Korsgaard (following Kant) says we must, we need not commit ourselves to valuing only the cognitive capacities of humanity but also its (relatively) subjective elements. This directly relates to the nature of autonomy, for the question of whether moral obligation rests upon and contains affective elements depends on the conception of autonomy at work and whether affective elements are included in the types of reflective judgments that form its core.

A second question is this: since the reflection that is involved in autonomy (and which, according to this view, is the source of normativity) need only be hypothetical reflection upon one's desires and mental capacities, then the question arises: under what conditions is this hypothetical reflection meant to take place? If the capacity for reflection is the seat of obligation, then we must ask if the conditions under which such hypothetical reflection takes place are idealized in any sense — if they are assumed to be reasonable for example. Are we considering merely the reflections the (actual) person would make were she to turn her attention to the question, no matter how unreasonable such reflections might be? If so, why should we think this grounds obligations? If we assume they are reasonable, then under some conditions moral obligations are not imposed by the actual self but rather by an idealized, more rational self. This implies that morality is not literally self-imposed if by “self” one means the actual set of judgments made by the agent in question. Indeed, a Platonist/realist about moral value could claim that the objective values which (according to the theory) apply to all agents independent of choice are in fact “self-imposed” in this idealized sense: they would be imposed were the person to reflect on the matter, acting as a perfectly reasonable agent. This shows the complex and potentially problematic implications of this ambiguity.

This points to the question of whether autonomy can be the seat of moral obligation and respect if autonomy is conceived in a purely procedural manner. If no substantive commitments or value orientations are included in the conceptual specification of autonomy, then it is unclear how this capacity grounds any particular substantive value commitments. On the other hand, if autonomy includes a specification of particular values in its conditions — that the autonomous person must value her own freedom for example — then it turns out that moral obligation (and respect) attaches only to those already committed in this way, and not more generally to all rational agents as such (as traditionally advertised by the view). This echoes, of course, Hegel's critique of Kant.

These difficulties point to ambiguities in autonomy-based moral views, ones which may well be clarified in further developments of those theories. They also pick up on traditional problems with Kantian ethics (though there are many other such difficulties not mentioned here). Before leaving moral philosophy, we should consider ethical views which focus on autonomy but which do not depend directly on a Kantian framework.

2.1 Autonomy as an Object of Value

Autonomy can play a role in moral theory without that theory being fully Kantian in structure. For example, it is possible to argue that personal autonomy has intrinsic value independent of a fully worked out view of practical reason. Following John Stuart Mill, for example, one can claim that autonomy is “one of the elements of well-being” (Mill 1859/1975, ch. III). Viewing autonomy as an intrinsic value or as a constitutive element in personal well-being in this way opens the door to a generally consequentialist moral framework while paying heed to the importance of self-government to a fulfilling life (for discussion see Sumner 1996).

It may also be unclear why autonomy — viewed here as the capacity to reflect on and endorse one's values, character and commitments — should have value independent of the results of exercising that capacity. Why is one person's autonomy intrinsically valuable when she uses it to, say, harm herself or make rash or morally skewed choices? More generally, how can we take account of the systematic biases and distortions that plague typical human reasoning in valuing people's capacity to make decisions for themselves (see, e.g., Conly 2013)? This question becomes more acute as we consider ways that autonomy can obtain in degrees, for then it is unclear why personal autonomy should be seen as equally valuable in persons who display different levels of it (or different levels of those abilities that are its conditions, such as rationality).

Indeed, autonomy is often cited as the ground of treating all individuals equally from a moral point of view. But if autonomy is not an all-or-nothing characteristic, this commitment to moral equality becomes problematic (Arneson 1999). It can be argued that insofar as the abilities required for autonomy, such as rational reflectiveness, competences in carrying out one's decisions, and the like, vary across individuals (within or between species as well), then it is difficult to maintain that all autonomous beings have equal moral status or that their interests deserve the same weight in considering decisions that affect them.

The move that must be made here, I think, picks up on Korsgaard's gloss on Kantianism and the argument that our reflective capacities ultimately ground our obligations to others and, in turn, others' obligations to regard us as moral equals. Arneson argues, however, that people surely vary in this capacity as well — the ability to reflectively consider options and choose sensibly from among them. Recall what we said above concerning the ambiguities of Korsgaard's account concerning the degree to which the self-reflection that grounds obligation is idealized at all. If it is, then it is not the everyday capacity to look within ourselves and make a choice that gives us moral status but the more rarified ability to do so rationally, in some full sense. But we surely vary in our ability to reach that ideal, so why should our autonomy be regarded as equally worthy?

The answer may be that our normative commitments do not arise from our actual capacities to reflect and to choose (though we must have such capacities to some minimal degree), but rather from the way in which we must view ourselves as having these capacities. We give special weight to our own present and past decisions, so that we continue on with projects and plans we make because (all other things being equal) we made them, they are ours, at least when we do them after some reflective deliberation. The pull that our own decisions have on our ongoing projects and actions can only be explained by the assumption that we confer status and value on decisions simply because we reflectively made them (perhaps, though, in light of external, objective considerations). This is an all-or-nothing capacity and hence may be enough to ground our equal status even if perhaps, in real life, we exercise this capacity to varying degrees.[3] Much has been written about conceptions of well being that rehearse these worries (see Sumner 1996, Griffin 1988). Such a view might be buttressed with the idea that the attribution of autonomous agency, and the respect that purportedly goes with it, is itself a normative stance, not a mere observation of how a person actually thinks and acts (for discussion of this position see Christman 2005 and Korsgaard 2014)

2.2 Autonomy and Paternalism

Autonomy is the aspect of persons that undue paternalism offends against. Paternalistic interventions can be both interpersonal (governed by social and moral norms) and a matter of policy (mediated by formal or legal rules). Such interventions are identified not by the kind of acts they involve but by the justification given for them, so that paternalism involves interference with a person's actions or knowledge against that person's will for the purpose of advancing that person's good. Respect for autonomy is meant to prohibit such interventions because they involve a judgment that the person is not able to decide for herself how best to pursue her own good. Autonomy is the ability to so decide, so for the autonomous subject of such interventions paternalism involves a lack of respect for autonomy. See also Paternalism.

But as our discussion of the nature of autonomy indicated, it is often unclear exactly what that characteristic involves. Important in this context is whether autonomy can be manifested in degrees — whether the abilities and capacities that constitute autonomy obtain all at once or progressively. If the latter is the case, then it is unclear that a blanket prohibition against paternalism is warranted. Some people will be less able to judge for themselves what their own good is and hence be more susceptible to (justified) paternalistic intervention (Conly 2013).

Often such an obligation toward another person requires us to treat her as autonomous, independent of the extent to which she is so concerning the choice in question. At least this is the case when a person is autonomous above a certain threshold: she is an adult, not under the influence of debilitating factors, and so on. I might know that a person is to some degree under the sway of external pressures that are severely limiting her ability to govern her life and make independent choices. But as long as she has not lost the basic ability to reflectively consider her options and make choices, if I intervene against her will (for her own good), I show less respect for her as a person than if I allow her to make her own mistakes. (Which is not to say, of course, that intervention in such cases might not, in the end, be justified; only that something is lost when it is engaged in, and what is lost is a degree of interpersonal respect we owe each other.)

However, as we saw in the last section, this move depends on the determination of basic autonomy and an argument that such a threshold is non-arbitrary. Also relevant here is the question of procedural versus substantive autonomy as the ground of the prohibition of paternalism. For if by “autonomy” we mean the ability to govern oneself no matter how depraved or morally worthless are the options being exercised, it is unclear that the bar to paternalism (and respect for persons generally) retains its normative force. As I mentioned above, the response to this challenge must be that the decision making capacity itself is of non-derivative value, independent of the content of those decisions, at least if one wishes to avoid the difficulties of positing a substantive (and hence non-neutral) conception of autonomy as the basis for interpersonal respect.

This is merely a sampling of some of the central ways that the idea of autonomy figures in moral philosophy. Not discussed here are areas of applied ethics, for example in medical ethics, where respect for autonomy grounds such principles as that of informed consent. Such contexts illustrate the fundamental value that autonomy generally is thought to represent as expressive of one of the fundamentals of moral personhood.

3. Autonomy in Social and Political Philosophy

3.1 Autonomy and the Foundations of Liberalism

The conception of the autonomous person plays a variety of roles in various constructions of liberal political theory (for recent discussion, see, e.g., Coburn 2010 and the essays in Christman and Anderson, eds. 2005). Principally, it serves as the model of the person whose perspective is used to formulate and justify political principles, as in social contract models of principles of justice (Rawls 1971). Also (and correspondingly) it serves as the model of the citizen whose basic interests are reflected in those principles, such as in the claim that basic liberties, opportunities, and other primary goods are fundamental to flourishing lives no matter what moral commitments, life plans, or other particulars of the person might obtain (Kymlicka 1989, 10–19, Waldron 1993: 155–6).[4] Moreover, autonomy is ascribed to persons (or projected as an ideal) in order to delineate and critique oppressive social conditions, liberation from which is considered a fundamental goal of justice (whether or not those critiques are described as within the liberal tradition or as a specific alternative to it) (cf. Keornahan 1999, Cornell 1998, Young 1990, Gould 1988; cf. also Hirschmann 2002, 1–29).

For our purposes here, liberalism refers generally to that approach to political power and social justice that determines principles of right (justice) prior to, and largely independent of, determination of conceptions of the good (though see Liberalism; see also Christman 2002, ch. 4). This implies that the liberal conception of justice, and the legitimation of political power more generally, can be specified and justified without crucial reference to controversial conceptions of value and moral principles (what Rawls calls “comprehensive moral conceptions” (Rawls 1993, 13–15). The fact of permanent pluralism of such moral conceptions is therefore central to liberalism.[5]

One manner in which debates concerning autonomy directly connect to controversies within and about liberalism concerns the role that state neutrality is to play in the justification and application of principles of justice. Neutrality is a controversial standard, of course, and the precise way in which liberal theory is committed to a requirement of neutrality is complex and controversial (see Raz 1986, 110–64, Waldron 1993, 143–67). The question to be asked here is whether the conception of autonomy utilized in liberal theories must itself attempt to be neutral concerning various conceptions of morality and value, or, alternatively, does the reliance on autonomy in the justification and specification of liberal theories of justice render them non-neutral simply because of this reliance (no matter how “neutral” the conception of autonomy utilized turns out to be).

Let us consider this first question and in so doing revisit the issue of whether the independence implicit in autonomy should best be conceived in a purely “procedural” manner or more substantively. Recall that some theorists view autonomy as requiring minimal competence (or rationality) along with authenticity, where the latter condition is fleshed out in terms of the capacity to reflectively endorse (or not be alienated from) aspects of oneself. This view can be called “proceduralist” because it demands that the procedure by which a person comes to identify a desire (or trait) as her own is what is crucial in the determination of its authenticity and hence autonomy. This conception of autonomy is adopted, according to its defenders, because doing so is the only way to ensure that autonomy is neutral toward all conceptions of value and the good that reasonable adults may come to internalize (Dworkin 1989).

Critics of this view have pointed to cases where it is imagined that persons adopt what we all would call oppressive and overly restrictive life situations but in a way that meets the minimal conditions of autonomy on proceduralist accounts, so that on such accounts they count as autonomous because of the self-governing processes by which they entered such oppressive conditions. These critics argue that any conception of autonomy that ascribes that trait to such people is wrongly conceived (Benson 1987, MacKenzie & Stoljar 2001b, Waller 1993, Oshana 1998, Stoljar 2000). On the basis of such a judgment, they argue that normatively substantive conditions should be added to the requirements of autonomy, conditions such as the ability to recognize and follow certain moral or political norms (See Benson 1987, Wolf 1980; for criticism, see Berofsky 1995, ch. 7). This criticism suggests that considerations concerning the autonomous self cannot avoid questions of identity and hence whether the self of self-government can be understood independently of the (perhaps socially defined) values in terms of which people conceive of themselves; this is a subject to which we now turn.

3.2 Identity and Conceptions of the Self

Autonomy, as we have been describing it, certainly attaches paradigmatically to individual persons; it is not (in this usage) a property of groups or peoples. So the autonomy that grounds basic rights and which connects to moral responsibility, as this concept is thought to do, is assigned to persons without essential reference to other people, institutions, or traditions within which they may live and act. Critics claim, however, that such a view runs counter to the manner in which most of us (or all of us in some ways) define ourselves, and hence diverges problematically from the aspects of identity that motivate action, ground moral commitments, and by which people formulate life plans. Autonomy, it is argued, implies the ability to reflect wholly on oneself, to accept or reject one's values, connections, and self-defining features, and change such elements of one's life at will. But we are all not only deeply enmeshed in social relations and cultural patterns, we are also defined by such relations, some claim(Sandel 1982, 15–65). For example, we use language to engage in reflection but language is itself a social product and deeply tied to various cultural forms. In any number of ways we are constituted by factors that lie beyond our reflective control but which nonetheless structure our values, thoughts, and motivations (Taylor 1991, 33f; for discussion see Bell 1993, 24–54). To say that we are autonomous (and hence morally responsible, bear moral rights, etc.) only when we can step back from all such connections and critically appraise and possibly alter them flies in the face of these psychological and metaphysical realities.[6]

In a different manner, critics have claimed that the liberal conception of the person, reflected in standard models of autonomy, under-emphasizes the deep identity-constituting connections we have with gender, race, culture, and religion, among other things. Such “thick” identities are not central to the understanding of the self-governing person who, according to standard liberal models, is fully able to abstract from such elements of her self-concept and to either identify with or to reject such them. But such an ideal too narrowly valorizes the life of the cosmopolitan “man” — the world traveler who freely chooses whether to settle into this or that community, identify with this or that group, and so on (see Young 1991, Alcoff 2006 and Appiah 2010; for discussion, see Meyers, 2000b).

These challenges have also focused on the relation of the self to its culture (Margalit and Raz, 1990, Tamir 1993). What is at issue from a policy perspective is that emphasis on the individual's self-government, with the cosmopolitan perspective that this entails, makes it difficult if not impossible to ground rights to the protection and internal self- government of traditional cultures themselves (Kymlicka, 1995). This is problematic in that it excludes from the direct protection of liberal policies those individuals and groups whose self-conceptions and value commitments are deeply constituted by cultural factors. Or, conversely, the assumption that the autonomous person is able to separate himself from all cultural commitments forestalls moves to provide state protection for cultural forms themselves, insofar as such state policies rest on the value of autonomy.

There have been many responses to these charges on behalf of a liberal outlook (e.g., Kymlicka, 1989, Gutman, 1985, Appiah 2005; for a general response to question of cultural identities see Kymlicka 1997). The most powerful response is that autonomy need not require that people be in a position to step away from all of their connections and values and to critically appraise them. Mere piecemeal reflection is all that is required. As Kymlicka puts it: “No particular task is set for us by society, and no particular cultural practice has authority that is beyond individual judgement and possible rejection” (Kymlicka, 1989:, 50).

There is a clarification that is needed in this exchange, however. For insofar as defenders of liberal principles (based on the value of autonomy) claim that all aspects of a person's self-concept be subject to alteration in order to manifest autonomy, they needlessly exaggerate the commitments of the liberal position. For such a view is open to the charge that liberal conceptions fail to take seriously the permanent and unalterable aspects of the self and its social position (Young, 1990, 46). Our embodiment, for example, is often not something which we can alter other than marginally, and numerous other self-defining factors such as sexual orientation (for some), native language, culture and race, are not readily subject to our manipulation and transformation, even in a piecemeal manner. To say that we are heteronomous because of this is therefore deeply problematic. What must be claimed by the defender of autonomy-based liberalism is that the ability in question is to change those aspects of oneself from which one is deeply alienated (or with which one does not identify, etc.). For in those cases where, upon reflection, one experiences one's body, culture, race, or sexuality as an external burden constricting one's more settled and authentic nature, and still one cannot alter that factor, then one lacks autonomy relative to it (see Christman, 2001, 2009 ch. 6). But if one feels fully at home within those unalterable parameters one does not lack autonomy because of that unalterability

3.3 Relational Autonomy

Several writers have claimed that proceduralist accounts of autonomy would wrongly attribute autonomy to those whose restricted socialization and stultifying life conditions pressure them into internalizing opressive values and norms, for example women who have internalized the belief in the social authority of husbands, or that only by having and raising children are their lives truly complete, and the like. If such women reflect on these values they may well endorse them, even if doing so is free of any specific reflection-inhibiting conditions. But such women surely lack autonomy, it is claimed; so only if autonomy includes a requirement that one be able to recognize basic value claims (such as the person's own equal moral standing) will that concept be useful in describing the oppressive conditions of a patriarchal society (see, e.g., Oshana, 1998, Stoljar, 2000; for discussion see Christman 1995, Benson, 1990, Friedman, 2000, Meyers, 1987, 1989).[7]

These and related considerations have sparked some to develop an alternative conception of autonomy meant to replace allegedly overly individualistic notions. This replacement has been called “relational autonomy” (MacKenzie and Stoljar, 2000a). Spurred by feminist critiques of traditional conceptions of autonomy and rights (Nedelsky, 1989, Code, 1991), relational conceptions of autonomy stress the ineliminable role that relatedness plays in both persons' self- conceptions, relative to which autonomy must be defined, and the dynamics of deliberation and reasoning. These views offer a provocative alternative to traditional models of the autonomous individual, but it must be made clear what position is being taken on the issue: on the one hand, relational accounts can be taken as resting on a non-individualist conception of the person and then claim that insofar as autonomy is self-government and the self is constituted by relations with others, then autonomy is relational; or these accounts may be understood as claiming that whatever selves turn out to be, autonomy fundamentally involves social relations rather than individual traits (Oshana, 2006). Some such views also waiver between claiming that social and personal relations play a crucial causal role in the development and enjoyment of autonomy and claiming that such relations constitute autonomy (for discussion see Mackenzie and Stoljar, 2000b, 21–26; for a recent overview, see Mackenzie 2014).

Another relational element to autonomy that has been developed connects social support and recognition of the person's status to her capacities for self-trust, self-esteem, and self-respect. The core argument in these approaches is that autonomy requires the ability to act effectively on one's own values (either as an individual or member of a social group), but that oppressive social conditions of various kinds threaten those abilities by removing one's sense of self-confidence required for effective agency. Social recognition and/or support for this self-trusting status is required for the full enjoyment of these abilities (see Anderson and Honneth 2005, Grovier 1993, Benson 2005, McCleod and Sherwin 2005, and Westlund 2014).

These claims often are accompanied with a rejection of purportedly value-neutral, proceduralist accounts of autonomy, even those that attempt to accommodate a fully social conception of the self. One question that arises with relational views connected to self-trust in this way, is why, exactly such relations are seen as conceptually constitutive of autonomy rather than contributory to it (and its development), where the self-confidence or self-trust in question is the core element to which these sorts of social relations are an important (albeit contingent) contributor. Another question to be considered arises from those cases where self-trust is established despite lack of social recognition, as when runaway slaves manage to heroically push on with their quest for freedom while facing violent denials from surrounding others (and surrounding social structures) that they enjoy the status of a full human being capable of authentic decision making. Finally, self-trust is not always merited: consider the brash teenager who insists on exercising social independence based on her unwarranted confidence in her abilities to make good judgments (see Mackenzie 2008, n. 36).

Nevertheless, these approaches have all importantly shifted philosophical attention concerning autonomy to the social and interpersonal dynamics that shape its enjoyment, connecting ideas about autonomy with broader issues of social justice, recognition, and social practices. This brings us back, then, to considerations of the liberal project and its potential limitations, where autonomy remains central.

3.4 Autonomy, Liberalism, and Perfectionism

As noted earlier, there are various versions of liberal political philosophy. All of them, however, are committed to a conception of political legitimacy in which political power and authority is justified only if such authority is acceptable to all citizens bound by it (see Rawls 1993, 144–50). This connects to a broader view of the foundations of value that at least some liberal theorists present as central to that tradition. That is the claim that values are valid for a person only if those values are or can be reasonably endorsed by the person in question. By extension, principles guiding the operation of institutions of social and political power — what Rawls calls the institutions of the basic structure (Rawls 1993, 258) — are legitimate only if they can be endorsed in this way by those subject to them. In this way, liberalism (in most of its forms) is committed to what some have called the “endorsement constraint” (Kymlicka 1989, 12f, R. Dworkin 2000, 216–18).

Models of autonomy considered above include a condition that mirrors this constraint, in that a person is autonomous relative to some action-guiding norm or value only if, upon critical reflection of that value, she identifies with it, approves of it, or does not feel deeply alienated from it. Combining this view with the endorsement constraint, liberalism carries the implication that autonomy is respected only when guiding values or principles in a society can be embraced in some way by those governed by them. This will connect directly to the liberal theory of legitimacy to be discussed below.

Perfectionists reject this set of claims. Perfectionism is the view that there are values valid for an individual or a population even when, from the subjective point of view of those agents or groups, that value is not endorsed or accepted (Wall 1998, Sumner 1996, 45–80, Hurka 1993, Sher 1997; see also Perfectionism). In short, it is the view that there are entirely objective values. While there are perfectionist liberals, this view generally resists the liberal claim that the autonomous acceptance of the central components of political principles is a necessary condition for the legitimacy of those principles. Moreover, perfectionists question the liberal commitment to neutrality in the formulation and application of political principles (Hurka 1993, 158–60).

Perfectionists specifically target the liberal connection between respect for autonomy and neutrality of political principles (Wall 1998, 125–204). For many, liberalism rests on the value of individual autonomy, but this reliance either assumes that respect for autonomy is merely one value among others in the liberal view, or autonomy has overriding value. In either case, however, neutrality is not supported. If autonomy is merely one value among others, for example, then there will clearly be times when state support of those other values will override respect for autonomy (paternalistic restrictions imposed to promote citizen safety, for example) (Sher 1997, 45–105, Hurka 1993, 158–60). On the other hand, autonomy could be seen as an absolute constraint on the promotion of values, or, more plausibly, as a constitutive condition of the validity of all values for a person, as the endorsement constraint implies. Perfectionists reply, however, that this is itself a controversial value position, one that may not find unqualified general support (Hurka 1993, 148–52, Sher 1997, 58–60, Sumner 1996, 174–83; cf. Griffin 1986, 135– 36). To answer these objections, one must turn to consideration of the liberal principle of legitimacy. For the claim that liberals make concerning the limits of state promotion of the good — a limit set by respect for autonomy — depends heavily on their view about the ultimate ground of political power.

3.5 Autonomy and Political Liberalism

Liberalism is generally understood to arise historically out of the social contract tradition of political philosophy and hence rests on the idea of popular sovereignty. The concept of autonomy, then, figures centrally in at least one dominant strand in this tradition, the strand the runs through the work of Kant. The major alternative version of the liberal tradition sees popular sovereignty as basically a collective expression of rational choice and that the principles of the basic institutions of political power are merely instrumental in the maximization of aggregate citizen welfare (or, as with Mill, a constitutive element of welfare broadly considered).

But it is the Kantian brand of liberalism that places autonomy of persons at center stage. Rawls's Theory of Justice was seen as the contemporary manifestation of this Kantian approach to justice, where justice was conceived as those principles that would be chosen under conditions of unbiased rational decision-making (from behind the veil of ignorance). The original position where such principles would be chosen was said by Rawls to mirror Kant's Categorical Imperative. That is, it is a device in which persons can choose principles to impose upon themselves in a way which is independent of contingencies of social position, race, sex, or conception of the good (Rawls 1971, 221–27). But as is well known, the Kantian foundations of Rawls's theory of justice rendered it vulnerable to the charge that it was inapplicable to those populations (all modern populations in fact) where deep moral pluralism abounds. For under such conditions, no theory of justice which rests on a metaphysically grounded conception of the person could claim full allegiance from members of a population whose deep diversity causes them to disagree about metaphysics itself, as well as about moral frameworks and conceptions of value related to it. For this reason, Rawls developed a new (or further developed) understanding of the foundations of his version of liberalism, a political conception (Rawls 1993).

Under political liberalism, autonomy of persons is postulated, not as a metaphysically grounded “fact” about moral personality or practical reason as such, but rather as one of several “device[s] of representation” under which diverse citizens can focus on the methods of derivation (such as the original position) for substantive principles of justice (Rawls 1999, 303–58). Justice is achieved only when an overlapping consensus among people moved by deeply divergent but reasonable comprehensive moral views can be attained, a consensus in which such citizens can affirm principles of justice from within those comprehensive views.

Political Liberalism shifts the focus from a philosophical conception of justice, formulated abstractly and meant to apply universally, to a practical conception of legitimacy where consensus is reached without pretension of deep metaphysical roots for the principles in question. More than merely a “modus vivendi” for the participating parties, justice must be affirmed in a way that finds a moral basis for all participating citizens, albeit from different frameworks of value and moral obligation. The operation of public reason and deliberation, then, serves as the means by which such a consensus might be established, and hence public discussion and democratic institutions must be seen as a constitutive part of the justification of principles of justice rather than merely a mechanism for collective determination of the social good.

But the role of autonomy in the specification of this picture should not be under- emphasized (or the controversies it invites ignored). For such a consensus counts as legitimate only when achieved under conditions of free and authentic affirmation of shared principles. Only if the citizens see themselves as fully able to reflectively endorse or reject such shared principles, and to do so competently and with adequate information and range of options, can the overlapping political consensus step beyond the purely strategic dynamics of a modus vivendi and ground legitimate institutions of political power.

Therefore, social conditions that hamper the equal enjoyment of capacities to reflectively consider and (if necessary) reject principles of social justice, due, say, to extreme poverty, disability, ongoing injustice and inequality, or the like, restrict the establishment of just principles. Autonomy, then, insofar as that concept picks out the free reflective choice operating in the establishment of legitimacy, is basic to, and presupposed by, even such non-foundational (political) conceptions of justice.

Critics of political liberalism arise from several quarters. However, among the objections to it that focus on autonomy are those that question whether a political conception of legitimacy that rests on shared values can be sustained without the validity of those values being seen as somehow objective or fundamental, a position that clashes with the purported pluralism of political liberalism. Otherwise, citizens with deeply conflicting worldviews could not be expected to affirm the value of autonomy except as a mere modus vivendi (see, e.g., Wall 2009; cf. also Larmore 2008, 146–6). A line of response to this worry that could be pursued would be one that claimed that values that amount to autonomy (in some conceptualization of that idea) are already functional in the social structures and cultural practices of otherwise defensible democratic practices (as well as some critical projects that emphasize oppression and domination, as we saw above). This point raises the issue, to which we now turn, of the connection between autonomy, political liberalism, and democracy.

3.6 Autonomy, Justice and Democracy

In closing, we should add a word about the implications of political liberalism for the traditional division between liberal justice and democratic theory. I say “division” here, but different views of justice and democracy will convey very different conceptions of the relation between the two (see Christiano 1996, Lakoff 1996). But traditionally, liberal conceptions of justice have viewed democratic mechanisms of collective choice as essential but highly circumscribed by the constitutional provisions that principles of justice support. Individual rights and freedoms, equality before the law, and various privileges and protections associated with citizen autonomy are protected by principles of justice and hence not subject to democratic review, on this approach (Gutmann 1993).

However, liberal conceptions of justice have themselves evolved (in some strains at least) to include reference to collective discussion and debate (public reason) among the constitutive conditions of legitimacy. It could be claimed, then, that basic assumptions about citizens' capacities for reflective deliberation and choice — autonomy — must be part of the background conditions against which an overlapping consensus or other sort of political agreement concerning principles of justice is to operate.

Some thinkers have made the connection between individual or “private” autonomy and collective or “public” legitimacy — prominent, most notably Habermas (Habermas 1994). On this view, legitimacy and justice cannot be established in advance through philosophical construction and argument, as was thought to be the case in natural law traditions in which classical social contract theory flourished and which is inherited (in different form) in contemporary perfectionist liberal views. Rather, justice amounts to that set of principles that are established in practice and rendered legitimate by the actual support of affected citizens (and their representatives) in a process of collective discourse and deliberation (see e.g., Fraser 1997, 11–40 and Young 2000). Systems of rights and protections (private, individual autonomy) will necessarily be protected in order to institutionalize frameworks of public deliberation (and, more specifically, legislation and constitutional interpretation) that render principles of social justice acceptable to all affected (in consultation with others) (Habermas 1994, 111).

This view of justice, if at all acceptable, provides an indirect defense of the protection of autonomy and, in particular, conceptualizing autonomy in a way that assumes reflective self- evaluation. For only if citizen participants in the public discourse that underlies justice are assumed to have (and provided the basic resources for having) capacities for competent self- reflection, can the public defense and discussion of competing conceptions of justice take place (cf. Gaus 1996, Parts II and III, Gaus 2011). Insofar as autonomy is necessary for a functioning democracy (considered very broadly), and the latter is a constitutive element of just political institutions, then autonomy must be seen as reflective self-appraisal (and, I would add, non-alienation from central aspects of one's person) (see Cohen 2002, Richardson 2003).

This approach to justice and autonomy, spelled out here in rough and general form, has certainly faced criticism. In particular, those theorists concerned with the multi-dimensional nature of social and cultural “difference” have stressed how the conception of the autonomous person assumed in such principles (as well as criteria for rational discourse and public deliberation) is a contestable ideal not internalized by all participants in contemporary political life (see, e.g., Brown 1995, Benhabib 1992). Others motivated by post-modern considerations concerning the nature of the self, rationality, language, and identity, are also suspicious of the manner in which the basic concepts operative in liberal theories of justice (“autonomy” for example) are understood as fixed, transparent, and without their own political presuppositions (see, e.g., Butler 1990; for general discussion see White 1990).

These charges are stated here much too generally to give an adequate response in this context. But the challenge remains for any theory of justice which rests on a presumption of the normative centrality of autonomy. To be plausible in a variously pluralistic social setting, such a view must avoid the twin evils of forcibly imposing a (reasonably) contested value on resistant citizens, on the one hand, and simply abandoning all normative conceptions of social order in favor of open ended struggle for power on the other. The view that individuals ought to be treated as, and given the resources to become, autonomous in one of the minimal senses outlined here will, I submit, be a central element in any political view that steers between the Scylla of oppressive forms of perfectionism and the Charybdis of interest-group power politics.

Bibliography

  • Alcoff, Linda Martin (2006). Visible Identities: Race, Gender and the Self, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2005). The Ethics of Identity, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • ––– (2001). “(2010). Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, New York: Norton.
  • Arneson, Richard (1991). “Autonomy and Preference Formation,” in Jules Coleman and Allen Buchanan, eds. In Harm's Way: Essays in Honor of Joel Feinberg, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 42–73.
  • ––– (1999). “What, if Anything, Renders All Humans Morally Equal?,” in D. Jamieson (ed.), Singer and his Critics, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 103–28.
  • Arpaly, Nomy (2004). Unprincipled Virtue, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Atkins, Kim (2008). Narrative Identity and Moral Identity: A Practical Perspective, New York: Routledge.
  • Baumann, Holgar (2008). “Reconsidering Relational Autonomy. Personal Autonomy for Socially Embedded and Temporally Extended Selves,” Analyse and Kritik, 30: 445–468.
  • Bell, Daniel (1993). Communitarianism and its Critics, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Benhabib, Seyla (1992). Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics, New York: Routledge.
  • Benn, Stanley (1988). A Theory of Freedom, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Benson, Paul (2005). “Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy,” in J.S. Taylor (ed.) (2005), pp. 124–42.
  • ––– (1994) “Autonomy and Self-Worth,” Journal of Philosophy, 91 (12): 650–668.
  • ––– (1990). “Feminist Second Thoughts About Free Agency,” Hypatia, 5 (3): 47–64.
  • ––– (1987). “Freedom and Value,” Journal of Philosophy, 84: 465–86.
  • Berlin, Isaiah (1969). “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Four Essays on Liberty, London: Oxford University Press, pp. 118–72.
  • Berofsky, Bernard (1995). Liberation from Self, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brighouse, Harry (2000). School Choice and Social Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Brown, Wendy (1995). States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Bushnell, Dana, ed. (1995). Nagging Questions, Savage, Md: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Butler, Judith (1990). Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, New York: Routledge.
  • Christiano, Thomas (1996). The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • Christiano, Thomas and John Christman, eds. (2009). Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophhy Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Christman, John (1991). “Autonomy and Personal History,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21 (1): 1–24.
  • ––– (1995). “Feminism and Autonomy,” in Bushnell (1995), pp. 17–39.
  • ––– (2001). “Liberalism, Autonomy, and Self-Transformation,” in Social Theory and Practice, 27 (2): 185–206.
  • ––– (2004). Social and Political Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction, London: Routledge.
  • ––– (2001). “(2005). “Autonomy, Self-knowledge and Liberal Legitimacy,” in Christman and Anderson (eds.) (2005), 330–57.
  • ––– (2009). The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– ed. (1989)The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Christman, John and Joel Anderson, eds. (2005). Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cochran, David (1999). The Color of Freedom, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
  • Coburn, Ben (2010). Autonomy and Liberalism, New York: Routledge.
  • Code, Lorraine (1991). “Second Persons,” in What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Cohen, Joshua (1996). “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy,” in Benhabib (ed.) (1996a), pp. 95–119.
  • ––– (2002). “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in James Bohman and William Rehg, eds., Deliberative Democracy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 67–92.
  • Conly, Sarah (2013). Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cornell, Drucilla (1998). At the Heart of Freedom, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Crittenden, Jack (1992). Beyond Individualism: Reconstituting the Liberal Self, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Crocker, Lawrence (1980). Positive Liberty, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Cuypers, Stefaan (2001). Self-Identity and Personal Autonomy, Hampshire, UK: Ashgate.
  • Cuypers, Stefaan E. and Haji, Ishtiyaque (2008). “Educating for Well-Being and Autonomy,” in Theory and Research in Education, 6 (1): 71–93.
  • Double, Richard (1992). “Two Types of Autonomy Accounts,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1): 65–80.
  • Dworkin, Gerald (1988). The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Dworkin, Ronald (2000). Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Elster, Jon (1983). Sour Grapes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Feinberg, Joel (1986). Harm to Self. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (Volume 3), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (1989). “Autonomy,” in Christman, ed. (1989), pp. 27–53.
  • Fischer, John Martin, ed. (1986). Moral Responsibility, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Fischer, John Martin and Mark Ravizza (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Flathman, Richard (1989). Toward A Liberalism, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Frankfurt, Harry (1987). “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” in The Importance of What We Care About, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1992). “The Faintest Passion,” Proceedings and Addresses of the Aristotelian Society, 49: 113–45.
  • Friedman, Marilyn (1986). “Autonomy and the Split-Level Self,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24 (1): 19–35.
  • ––– (1997). “Autonomy and Social Relationships: Rethinking the Feminist Critique,” in Meyers, ed. (1997), pp. 40–61.
  • ––– (1998). “Feminism, Autonomy, and Emotion,” in Norms and Values: Essays on the Work of Virginia Held, Joram Graf Haber, ed., Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • ––– (2000). “Autonomy, Social Disruption, and Women,” in MacKenzie and Stoljar, eds. (2000), pp. 35–51.
  • Gaus, Gerald F. (1996). Justificatory Liberalism, New York: Oxford University Press
  • ––– (2001). “(2011). The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Geuss, Raymond (2001). “Liberalism and Its Discontents,” Political Theory, 30(3): 320–39.
  • Gilligan, Carol (1982). In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Gould, Carol (1988). Rethinking Democracy: Freedom and Social Cooperation in Politics, Economy, and Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gray, John (1993). Post-Liberalism: Studies in Political Thought, New York: Routledge.
  • Griffin, James (1988). Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Grovier, Trudy (1993). “Self-Trust, Autonomy and Self-Esteem,” Hypatia, 8 (1): 99-119.
  • Gutman, Amy (1985). “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14 (3): 308–22.
  • ––– (1987). Democratic Education, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • ––– (1993). “Democracy,” in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 411–21.
  • Habermas, Jürgen (1994). Between Facts and Norms, William Rehg, trans., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Haworth, Lawrence (1986). Autonomy: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology and Ethics, New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Herman, Barbara (1993). The Practice of Moral Judgement, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Hill, Thomas (1987). “The Importance of Autonomy,” in Kittay and Meyers, ed. (1987), pp. 129–38.
  • ––– (1989). “The Kantian Conception of Autonomy,” in Christman, ed. (1989), pp. 91–105.
  • ––– (1991). Autonomy and Self Respect, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hirschmann, Nancy (2002). The Subject of Freedom: Toward A Feminist Theory of Freedom, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Hurka, Thomas (1993). Perfectionism, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Jaggar, Alison (1983). Feminist Politics and Human Nature, Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld.
  • Kant, Immanuel (1785/1983). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, in I. Kant , Ethical Philosophy, James W. Ellington, trans., Indianapolis, IA: Hackett Publishing Co.
  • ––– (1797/1999). Metaphysical Elements of Justice, John Ladd, ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
  • Kernohan, Andrew (1999). Liberalism, Equality, and Cultural Oppression, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kittay, Eva Feder and Diana T. Meyers (1987). Women and Moral Theory, Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Korsgaard, Christine M. (2014). “The Normative Constitution of Agency,” in Manuel Vargas and Gideon Yaffe, eds. Rational and Social Agency: The Philosophy of Michael Bratman, New York: Oxford University Press, 190–214.
  • ––– (2001). “(1996). The Sources of Normativity, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kymlicka, Will (1989). Liberalism, Community and Culture, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Lakoff, Sanford (1996) Democracy: History, Theory, Practice, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • Larmore, Charles (2008). The Autonomy of Morality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lehrer, Keith (1997). Self-Trust: A Study in Reason, Knowledge, and Autonomy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lindley, Richard (1986). Autonomy, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International.
  • MacIntyre, Alasdair (1984). After Virtue, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Mackenzie, Catriona (2008). “Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 39 (4): 512–33.
  • ––– (2014). “Three Dimensions of Autonomy: A Relational Analysis,” in Veltman and Piper, eds. (2014), 15–41.
  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar, eds. (2000a). Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2000b). “Introduction: Autonomy Refigured,” in Mackenzie and Stoljar, eds. (2000a): 3–31.
  • MacKinnon, Catherine (1989). Toward a Feminist Theory of the State, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Mahmoud, S. (2003). “Ethical Formation and Politics of Individual Autonomy in Contemporary Egypt,” Social Research, 70 (3): 837–866.
  • Margalit, Avashai and Joseph Raz (1990). “National Self-Determination,” Journal of Philosophy, 87(9): 439–61.
  • May, Thomas (1994). “The Concept of Autonomy,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 31 (2): 133–44.
  • McCallum, Gerald (1967). “Negative and Positive Freedom,” Philosophical Review, 76: 312–34.
  • McLeod, Carolyn and Susan Sherwin, “Relational Autonomy, Self-Trust, and Health Care for Patients Who Are Oppressed,” in MacKenzie and Stoljar, eds., 2000a, pp. 259–79.
  • Mele, Alfred R. (1991). “History and Personal Autonomy,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23: 271–80.
  • ––– (1995). Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Meyers, Diana T. (1987). “Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization,” Journal of Philosophy, 84: 619–28.
  • ––– (1989). Self, Society, and Personal Choice, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • ––– (1994). Subjection and Subjectivity: Psychoanalytic Feminism and Moral Philosophy, New York: Routledge.
  • ––– ed. (1997). Feminist Rethink the Self, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • ––– (2004). Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Mill, John Stuart (1859/1975). On Liberty, David Spitz, ed. New York: Norton.
  • Mills, Charles (1997). The Racial Contract, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Moon, J. Donald (1993). Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Nedelsky, Jennifer (1989). “Reconcieving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities,” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism, 1 (1): 7–36.
  • Nicholson, Linda, ed. (1990). Feminism/Postmodernism, New York: Routledge.
  • Noggle, R. (2005). “Autonomy and the Paradox of Self-Creation: Infinite Regresses, Finite Selves, and the Limits of Authenticity,” in J.S. Taylor, ed. (2005), pp. 87–108.
  • O'Neill, Onora (1989). Constructions of Reason: Explorations in Kant's Practical Philosophy, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Oshana, Marina (1998). “Personal Autonomy and Society,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 29 (1): 81–102.
  • ––– (2006). Personal Autonomy in Society, Hampshire, UK: Ashgate.
  • ––– (2005). “Autonomy and Self Identity,” in Christman and Anderson, eds. (2005), pp. 77–100.
  • Pearsall, Marilyn, ed. (1986). Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing.
  • Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice, Revised edition (1999) Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (1993). Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Raz, Joseph (1986). The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Richardson, Henry (2003). Democratic Autonomy: Public Reasoning about the Ends of Policy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ripstein, Arthur (1999). Equality, Responsibility, and the Law, Cambridge University Press.
  • Sandel, Michael J. (1982). Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition 1999.
  • Schneewind, J. B. (1998). The Invention of Autonomy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sher, George (1997). Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Stoljar, Natalie (2000). “Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,” in Mackenzie and Stoljar, eds. (2000a): 94–111.
  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, Happiness and Ethics, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Tamir, Yael (1993). Liberal Nationalism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Taylor, Charles (1989). “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Rosenblum (1989), pp. 159–82.
  • ––– (1991). The Ethics of Authenticity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (1992). Multiculturalism and the “Politics of Recognition,”, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Taylor, James Stacey, ed. (2005). Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Taylor, Robert (2005). “Kantian Personal Autonomy,” Political Theory, 33 (5): 602–628.
  • Thalberg, Irving (1989). “Hierarchical Analyses of Unfree Action,” reprinted in Christman (1989), pp. 123–136.
  • Veltman, Andrea and Mark Piper, eds. (2014). Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Waldron, Jeremy (1993). Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wall, Steven (1998). Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (2009). “Perfectionism in Politics: A Defense,” in Christiano and Christman, eds. 2009, pp. 99–118.
  • Westlund, Andrea (2014). “Autonomy and Self-Care,” in Veltman and Piper, eds. (2014), 181–98.
  • White, Stephen (1991). Political Theory and Post Modernism Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Williams, Bernard (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Wolf, Susan (1990). Freedom and Reason, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Wolff, Robert Paul (1970). In Defense of Anarchism, New York: Harper & Row.
  • Young, Iris Marion (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • ––– (2000). Inclusion and Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Young, Robert (1986). Autonomy: Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty, New York: St. Martin's Press.

Leave a Comment

(0 Comments)

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *